首页
登录
职称英语
When I was a graduate student in biochemistry at Tufts University School of
When I was a graduate student in biochemistry at Tufts University School of
游客
2023-12-05
30
管理
问题
When I was a graduate student in biochemistry at Tufts University School of Medicine, I read an abridged version of Montaigne’s Essays. My friend Margaret Rea and I spent hours wandering around Boston discussing the meaning and implications of the essays. Michel de Montaigne lived in the 16th century near Bordeaux, France. He did his writing in the southwest tower of his chateau, where he surrounded himself with a library of more than 1,000 books, a remarkable collection for that time. Montaigne posed the question, "What do I know?" By extension, he asks us all: Why do you believe what you think you know? My latest attempt to answer Montaigne can be found in Everyday Practice of Science: Where Intuition and Passion Meet Objectivity and Logic, originally published in January 2009 and soon to be out in paperback from the Oxford University Press.
Scientists tend to be glib about answering Montaigne’s question. After all, the success of technology testifies to the truth of our work. But the situation is more complicated.
In the idealized version of how science is done, facts about the world are waiting to be observed and collected by objective researchers who use the scientific method to carry out their work. But in the everyday practice of science, discovery frequently follows an ambiguous and complicated route. We aim to be objective, but we cannot escape the context of our unique life experiences. Prior knowledge and interests influence what we experience, what we think our experiences mean, and the subsequent actions we take. Opportunities for misinterpretation, error, and self-deception abound.
Consequently, discovery claims should be thought of as protoscience. Similar to newly staked mining claims, they are full of potential. But it takes communal scrutiny and acceptance to transform a discovery claim into a mature discovery. This is the credibility process, through which the individual researcher’s me, here, now becomes the community’s anyone, anywhere, anytime. Objective knowledge is the goal, not the starting point.
Once a discovery claim becomes public, the discoverer receives intellectual credit. But, unlike with mining claims, the community takes control of what happens next. Within the complex social structure of the scientific community, researchers make discoveries; editors and reviewers act as gatekeepers by controlling the publication process; other scientists use the new finding to suit their own purposes; and finally, the public (including other scientists) receives the new discovery and possibly accompanying technology. As a discovery claim works its way through the community, a dialectic of interaction and confrontation between shared and competing beliefs about the science and the technology involved transforms an individual’s discovery claim into the community’s credible discovery.
Two paradoxes infuse this credibility process. First, scientific work tends to focus on some aspect of prevailing knowledge that is viewed as incomplete or incorrect. Little reward accompanies duplication and confirmation of what is already known and believed. The goal is new-search, not research. Not surprisingly, newly published discovery claims and credible discoveries that appear to be important and convincing will always be open to challenge and potential modification or refutation by future researchers. Second, novelty itself frequently provokes disbelief. Nobel Laureate and physiologist Albert Szent-Gyorgyi once described discovery as "seeing what everybody has seen and thinking what nobody has thought." But thinking what nobody else has thought and telling others what they have missed may not change their views. Sometimes years are required for truly novel discovery claims to be accepted and appreciated.
In the end, credibility "happens" to a discovery claim — a process that corresponds to what philosopher Annette Baier has described as the commons of the mind. "We reason together, challenge, revise, and complete each other’s reasoning and each other’s conceptions of reason," she wrote in a book with that title. In the case of science, it is the commons of the mind where we find the answer to Montaigne’s question: Why do you believe what you think you know? [br] According to the third paragraph, the process of discovery is characterized by its
选项
A、uncertainty and complexity.
B、misconception and deceptiveness.
C、logicality and objectivity.
D、systematicness and regularity.
答案
A
解析
事实细节题。第三段第二句。But转折处指出在日常的实践中,科学发现常常遵循一个不确定而复杂的路径。题干中的process与文中的follows…route对应;因此答案选[A],uncertainty and complexity同义转述文中的ambiguous and complicated。该段末句提到的“误解、差错和自欺欺人时常发生”是我们以前的经验、知识和兴趣可能会对科学发现产生的影响,并不是其特点,故排除[B]。[C]和[D]是针对第三段首句提到的理想化状态下的科学发现所进行的错误推断。
转载请注明原文地址:https://tihaiku.com/zcyy/3247776.html
相关试题推荐
Amongthecollegestudentsnowadays,thereisatendencytoattachtoomuch
______isaprincipalrepresentativeofTheLondonSchool.A、SaussureB、HallidayC
JohnFirth,MalinowskiandHallidayaretherepresentativesof______School,kn
ThelargestuniversityinCanadais______A、UniversityofToronto.B、McGillUniv
Amongthecollegestudentsnowadays,thereisthetendencytoattachtoomuc
InawindowlessroomontheUniversityofCalifornia,Berkeley,campus,two
InawindowlessroomontheUniversityofCalifornia,Berkeley,campus,two
InawindowlessroomontheUniversityofCalifornia,Berkeley,campus,two
______isafamousworkwrittenbyJohnBunyan.A、AModestProposalB、TheSchoolf
Inrecentyears.Universitymerger,ahottopicbothonandoffcampus,has
随机试题
Ascientistoncesaidthatstudyingthestarsfromtheearthis【C1】______lo
施工单位应( )由项目部负责人主持召开一次安全生产例会,分析现场安全生产形势,
BFHR:
A.600 B.800 C.1000 D.1200
原发性血小板减少性紫癜A.血小板减少、BT延长、束臂试验阳性、PAIgG增高
( )是发生在流通领域的生产过程。A.物流的装卸搬运功能 B.物流的包装功能
下列场所,布置在高层民用建筑内时,应设置独立安全出口和疏散楼梯的有()。A.展览
某中学对高二学生进行文理科分班后,部分学生出现了学习成绩下降、情绪波动、同学关系
机构类家庭是指在儿童福利机构内,通过招募自然夫妇充当父母角色,配置()以上儿童
一般情况下,问卷的长度应控制的回答时间为( )A.0~30分钟 B.30~4
最新回复
(
0
)